Document Type : Scientific-research

Author

Assistant Professor, Institute of Humanities and Cultural Studies

Abstract

Wittgenstein begins the important work of his later period of thought, Philosophical Investigations, by critiquing Augustine's view of language. He goes on to show that Augustine's theory is based on a limited understanding and, in his words, an element of language that has limited it to the realm of communication and imagery. He also acknowledges Augustine's remarks as a way of ostensive teaching for language learning and has criticized this view. In this study, inferential qualitative method and using one of Augustine's completely specialized and philosophical works on the category of language and its relation to teaching, Teacher dialogue, has been shown that Wittgenstein's critiques of the picture theory of language, the criterion of meaning of language, and the theory of ostensive teaching and definition are, though not entirely, largely based on a limited understanding of Augustine's linguistic positions. Thus, the findings of the study suggest that Wittgenstein's criticism of Augustine's view of the narrative of his work was limited to the Confession book and since this autobiographical work is written more for the general audience and Augustine's aim was not to pose complicated and complex language issues and philosophize about them, Wittgenstein's understanding of the geography of Augustine's thought is strongly in doubt.

Keywords

Main Subjects

Augustine., (1991), Confessions. Trans. Henry Chadwick. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Augustine., (1975), De dialectica. trans. with introduction and notes by B. Darrell Jackson from the text edited by J. Pinborg, Dordrecht: Reidel.
Augustine., (1995), De doctrina Christiana. Trans. R. P. H. Green. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Augustine., (1995), The Teacher, In Against the Academicians; The Teacher. Trans, Peter King. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1995.
Augustine., (1963),  The Trinity. Trans. Stephen McKenna. Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press.
Baker and Hacker., (1980), Wittgenstein: Understanding and Meaning, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Bearsely, P., (1983), Augustine and Wittgenstine on Language, Philosophy, 58(224), pp. 229-236.
Burnyeat , M., (1987), Wittgenstein and Augustine De magistro. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary, Vol. 61, pp.1 – 24.
Cheung, L., (2014), Meaning Use and Ostensive Definition in Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigation, Philosophical Investigation, 37(4), pp. 350-362.
Erneling, C., (1993), Why First Language Learning Is Not Second Language Learning Wittgenstein's Rejection of St. Augustine's Concept of Learning, Interchange, 24(4), pp. 341-351.
Hanfling, O., (1989), Wittgenstein's Later Philosophy,  Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.
Harris, J., (1986), Language, Language Games and Ostensive Definition, Synthese, 69(1), pp. 41-49.
Kenny, A., (1974), The Ghost of the Tractatus, In: Understanding Wittgenstein, Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures, London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Kirwan, C., (2001), Augustine's Philosophy of Language, in The Cambridge Companion to Augustine, Cambridge: Cambridge.
Lugg, A., (2000), Wittgenstein's Investigations 1-33 a guide and interpretation, London: Routlesge.
McGinn, M., (1997), Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Wittgenstein and the Philosophical Investigation, London: Routledge.
Wittgenstein, L., (2009), Philosophical Investigations, Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
Wittgenstein, L., (2002), The Blue and Brown Books, Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.